The Making of the American Conservative Mind: National Review and its Times by Jeffrey Hart. ISI Books (Wilmington, Delaware), 410 pp., $28.00 cloth, 2006.
Jeffrey Hartâs The Making of the American Conservative Mind: National Review and Its Times is both a memoir of his years at National Review and a prescription for the sort of conservatism he favors. Hart succeeds at the former; the anecdotes he provides in abundance are almost always telling and often comic, and he has a gift for capturing strong personalities in a few phrases. William F. Buckley, Jr., the journalâs youthful founder, was âheretically American,â an aristocrat in âtaste, prose style, manners, yachting, wines, piano, and harpsichordâ whose âintermittent populismâ was memorably expressed in his willingness to be âgoverned by the first two thousand names in the Boston telephone directory than by the faculty of the Harvard University.â James Burnham was âdecorous, diplomatic, and elegant,â a man who confronted untoward political events âmuch as a botanist might regard a strangely colored and probably poisonous mushroom.â Willmoore Kendall, on the other hand, was a âdrastic personalityâ who was âalways on speaking terms with one personâ at the magazine, but âthis was not always the same person.â He knew that âAmerica is not an open society, and the Constitution was not written by Walt Whitman.â While defending his view of human nature as âMan against the Sky, creating himself is perpetual acts of choosing,â Frank Meyer âcombined physical and intellectual energy to a degree that could be overwhelming: wiry, in motion, pacing and talking, smoking and drinking bourbon.â Hart remembers Russell Kirk dazzling Dartmouth students by defending the notion that âthe chief motive in building character . . . is an unwillingness to disgrace oneâs ancestors,â a notion so foreign to his young audience that Kirk appeared âmore rebellious than Che Guevara and Malcolm X combined.â
Hart is much less successful in his more ambitious goal of persuading readers to accept his preferred version of conservatism on the basis of his intellectual history of âthe making of the American conservative mindâ over the last half-century as seen from the vantage point of National Review. His book highlights the views of four figures at National Review: James Burnham, Willmoore Kendall, Frank Meyer, and Russell Kirk. (Though he acknowledges the leadership of Buckley, Hart pays little attention to his ideas.) In Hartâs analysis, the views of Burnham and Kendall emerge as the most valuable. Though Frank Meyerâs âfusionismâ played a key role in the past, Hart thinks it is not particularly relevant today, while the Russell Kirk that appears in Hartâs presentation was always living in the past.
James Burnham is perhaps the most prominent among the four (though that is relative: outside his presumed conservative audience, none but perhaps Kirk remains in any sense well-known). Hart considers him âabsolutely central to National Reviewâ; Burnham was âindispensable,â perhaps because he articulated and defended the version of conservatism that Hart himself favors, a version Hart variously describes as âprudential conservatism,â âskeptical conservatismâ and âprudential and strategic conservatism.â This kind of conservatism leads âaway from alienation and toward engagement and centrality.â It rejects âidealist acts of political self-expression,â âsentimental illusionâ and âdreamy escapism.â What does this mean in specific terms? For Burnham, Hart reports approvingly, it meant a kind of Machiavellianism that sees âreligions and ideologies as masks for the reality of powerâ [original emphasis], which concludes that âpower thus is the real business of politics, the real business behind all the masks and rationalizations.â Hart praises Burnham for rescuing the conservative mind âfrom dogmatism and utopianism,â and, less successfully, struggling to keep the leadership of conservatism and the Republican party out of the hands of unsophisticated types who insist on injecting morality into politics and, worse, often base their morality on their religion. Burnhamâs view of ideology and even religion as âmasksâ led him, Hart notes approvingly, to favor politicians such as Nelson Rockefeller and Gerald Ford, even though, or perhaps because, such figures could not be accused of being âmovementâ conservatives, or perhaps of being conservative at all in any but the broadest sense.
Hart himself goes even further than his master in refusing to allow his own political opinions to be bound by any narrowâalmost any meaningfulâdefinition of conservatism. Hartâs rejection of what he considers âdogmatism and utopianismâ leaves him free to admire equally the conservatism of Franklin Roosevelt, Dwight Eisenhower and Ronald Reagan, since â[e]ach was essentially prudent, and each achieved his goals. Each, in his time, was conservative.â âPrudence,â for Hart, is the great conservative virtue in politics, a view he shares with Kirk, a conservative who, after all, titled an essay collection The Politics of Prudence. Hartâs version of prudence, however, seems to differ significantly from Kirkâs, just as Hartâs notion of what should constitute the âAmerican conservative mindâ differs greatly from that of the author of The Conservative Mind. Hartâs âprudenceâ emphasizes subordinating moral considerations to power calculations. Thus when Hart discusses Eisenhowerâs 1956 decision to refuse aid to Hungarians rebelling against Soviet Russiaâs domination, he does not defend the refusal to provide support as a sad necessity but celebrates it. Eisenhower, âa grand-scale realist, an unsentimental, icy, and even ruthless leader who saw the world as it wasâ out-Burnhamed Burnham, giving âa lesson in the cruelties sometimes entailed by Realpolitik.â Burnham, who, Hart explains, âproved emotionally fragile in the wake of Budapest,â was foolish enough to think that national âhonorâ was lost when America failed to help the Hungarian rebels. Hart provides a scorecard: âEisenhower 1, Burnham 0.â âWe were fortunate,â Hart concludes in affirming the presidentâs decision to refuse assistance to allies in both Hungary and Suez, âthat Eisenhower did not have one molecule of Churchillian poetry in his body or his mind.â
Perhaps. Yet one cannot help but think that there are times and places where âChurchillian poetryâ is valuable, even necessary, at least if one believes that human life involves more than power relationships. In The Politics of Prudence Russell Kirk celebrates âthe fortitude of Britain in general, and of Winston Churchill in particularâ in offering âsuccessful resistance to the enemies of a tolerable social orderâ and thus helping to sustain âorder, justice, and freedom.â Yet the British decision to go to war against Hitler rather than acquiesce in the Nazi takeover of Poland, as Britain had acquiesced in the takeover of Czechoslovakia, was not a prudent decision, not, at least, according to the Burnham-Hart notion of prudence. Winston Churchill wrote that the decision to finally resist the Nazi aggression was âtaken at the worst possible moment and on the least satisfactory ground.â And yet the decision was prudent according to Kirkâs notion of prudence, which requires that âany public measure ought to be judged by its probable long-term consequences, not merely by temporary advantage or popularity.â By this standard it was the Munich agreement that was imprudent, though it was extremely popular, took account of power relationships, and seemed to provide peace, at least for a timeâa âtemporary advantageâ that many thought worth seizing, whatever the eventual consequences.
Hartâs ideal conservative mind has no room for âpoetry,â Churchillian or otherwise, apparently because that might lead to âdreamy escapismâ or âsentimental illusion.â This rejection of the claims of what Kirk, following Edmund Burke, championed as the âmoral imagination,â seems odd from a distinguished literary critic. Once this aspect of Hartâs outlook is recognized, however, his failure to acknowledge or even to describe accurately the contribution of Kirk himself to âthe making of the American conservative mindâ becomes more understandable (though not more defensible). Hartâs praise of Kirk for his âself-creation,â calling him âa marvel,â a âself-invented work of art,â who could dazzle undergraduates, to whom he âembodied the romance of learning,â carries the implication that Kirkâs âaesthetic-Tory reverence for traditionâ is irrelevant to the sober consideration of practical matters that is the hallmark of Hartâs âprudential conservatism.â A reader who learns of Kirk only through The Making of the American Conservative Mind would view him as little more than an âantiquarian traditionalist,â whose âaesthetic attraction to the old and antiquatedâ might be charming, but who really has little to offer in regard to the serious business of establishing a âprudential, effective conservatism.â Even when Hart discusses the book from which he takes his own title, Kirkâs The Conservative Mind, he forgoes any substantive analysis but manages to suggest that the bookâs impact was due not so much to its intrinsic merit as merely to the year of its publication. If, as Hart finally concedes, Kirk nevertheless managed to create âa major statement,â he did so, Hart suggests, not because of his own thought but because Kirk âassembled an array of major conservative thinkersâ and then went about âvirtually anthologizing long passages.â
Hart means to join with Russell Kirk in championing âthe permanent thingsâ while distancing himself from what he views as Kirkâs âattraction to the old and antiquated,â but he devotes a good deal more verbal energy to the latter than to the former. In a chapter entitled âRussell Kirk vs. Frank Meyerâ Hart begins by presenting himself as an honest broker who admires both: âIt was a minor tragedy for National Review that Frank Meyer and Russell Kirk not only disagreed with each other but despised each other.â Yet when Hart sums up the two perspectives in a fictional exchange, Meyer is given the best line and Kirk an implausibly weak one:
Luther had said, âA mighty fortress is our God.â Kirk might say, âA mighty fortress is my library.â Meyer might reply, âA mighty fortress is my mind and my conscience.â
Those who have not read The Conservative Mind or any of Kirkâs other books could scarcely be faulted for assuming that Meyer was the deeper thinkerâcertainly âmy mindâ and âmy conscienceâ have more resonance than âmy library.â Yet those familiar with Kirkâs life and work would know that it would be quite appropriate to assign Meyerâs line to Kirk, and, for that matter, Lutherâs as well.
If Hart holds up Russell Kirkâs kind of conservatism as a temptation to be avoided, it is the putatively more disciplined conservatism of Burnham and Kendall that provides the model to be followed. Burnhamâs contribution to Hartâs âprudential conservatismâ is the reduction of politics to power relationships. Kendallâs âteaching,â in Hartâs presentation, is part of âthe skeptical-prudential conservative tradition in politicsâ that, most importantly for Hart, rejects âparadigm conservative politicsâ in favor of âconsensus, strategic politics.â This kind of conservatism rejects âthe absolutist dictates of some minorityâ; although âothers might find absolutes as they chose, . . . they were not part of conservative governing.â This rejection of moral absolutes unless supported by majority opinionââthe absolutistsâ position on whatever issue was before us had first to command a consensusââwas, according to Hart, âmost forcefully and thoroughly articulated by Willmoore Kendall.â Hartâs version of this philosophy includes the notion that opposition to abortion on demand is ânot conservative but Jacobinical.â The Roe decision, though an example of âjudicial overreach,â had, according to Hartâs self-described âBurkean analysisâ some justification, since âit did address the reality of the womenâs revolution, a social process with deep roots in actuality.â Hart not only considers recovering the once virtually universal view that abortion is legally and morally wrong âsurely a utopian notion,â he even questions the value of simply returning the question of abortion to state legislatures since âa checkerboard of state legislation might merely increase the value of Greyhound Bus stock.â
It is sometimes difficult to discern what is distinctively conservative about Hartâs conception of âthe American conservative mind.â He not only rates Franklin Roosevelt and Dwight Eisenhower with Ronald Reagan as conservative leaders, he finds that Bill Clinton in many ways exemplified a âprudential conservatismâ:
As a political leader, Clinton sought to capture the center while marginalizing the utopians and extremists in his own party. He was a man of compromise, conciliation, and a sense of contingency, preferring results to ideological satisfactions. . . . Clinton is even nowâdismaying to conservative partisansârising in general estimation, and no doubt will achieve a decent place in the judgment of history . . . his overall performance was better for the country than it looked at the time.
Even when Hart praises a principled conservative like Ronald Reagan, he praises him for qualities thathave little to do with conservatism. Reagan wasnât really serious about opposing abortion, Hart asserts approvingly; he âleaned libertarian.â Hartâs version of Reaganism is âat one with Whitmanâs open poem, William Jamesâs open philosophy, and Rooseveltâs âThe only thing we have to fear is fear itselfâ One cannot help but wonder what sort of conservatism whose highest praise for the most successful conservative president in recent decades is to align him with a trio of self-professed enemies of conservatism. Here Hart finds himself in opposition both to his mentors Burnham and Kendall and to his own assertion, noted above, that one of Kendallâs most valuable insights was his awareness that âAmerica is not an open society and the Constitution was not written by Walt Whitman.â
The philosophical confusion that impoverishes Jeffrey Hartâs âprudential conservatismâ is well illustrated by his coupling of a call for âa recovery of the great structure of metaphysicsâ with the suggestion a few pages later that âthe philosophy of William James, so distinctively American, might be the best guide, a philosophy always open to experience.â If Hart had taken The Conservative Mind more seriously, he might have been learned to be suspicious rather than enthusiastic about both Walt Whitman and William James from George Santayana, whom Kirk endorsed as an exemplar of cultural and philosophic conservatism. Santayana pointed out that Walt Whitmanâs achievement was to exemplify âthe poetry of barbarism,â a poetry ânot without its charmâ but achieving its effect by purposefully ignoring the achievements of civilization. As Santayana puts it, Whitman âaccomplished, by the sacrifice of almost every other good quality, something never so well done before. He has approached common life without bringing in his mind any higher standard by which to criticize it. . . . Being the poet of the average man, he wished all men to be specimens of that average.â Santayana pointed out that the âopen philosophyâ Hart admires prevented William James from learning from experienceââExperience seems to most of us to lead to conclusions, but [Jamesâs] empiricism has sworn never to draw them.â Thus in regard to religion, James âdid not really believe; he merely believed in the right of believing that you might be right if you believed.â
It is true that prudence is a great virtue in politics, and there is a good deal to be said in favor of âprudential conservatism.â Unfortunately, however, when prudence is detached from principle, it becomes mere expediency. The effect of Hartâs lively book is to commend a âprudential, effective conservatismâ whose effectiveness would, one fears, be measured not by its success in putting conservative principles into practiceâprudently of courseâbut simply by its success in winning elections. Hart warns against what he fears might be the decline of National Review from an earlier emphasis on philosophical questioning to a focus on âtopicality to the exclusion of serious reflection.â Yet Hartâs own baldly pragmatic preference for âresults to ideological satisfactionsâ seems to leave little room for philosophical or moral considerations.
Hart is a fine literary critic and an often thoughtful writer, and his book on National Review and its times deserves a wide audience. He is surely right when he argues that American conservatives should aim to govern responsibly rather than secede and isolate themselves in frustration or disgust from American politics. It would be a shame, however, if the intellectual, moral, and spiritual effort involved in âthe making of the American conservative mindâ were to lead to a result no more profound and no more thoughtful than his âprudential, effective conservatism.â
James Seaton is a professor of English at Michigan State University. He is the editor of a volume on George Santayana forthcoming in Yale University Pressâs âRethinking the Western Traditionâ series.